Simone de Beauvoir produced a massive body of work. Not only did she do it while being one of the preeminent scholars of her youth (and later) but also while playing a major part in being the architect of existentialism and modern-day definers of feminism.returnreturnThis book does not only play a key part in defining Beauvoir for who she was by delving into recent discoveries, e.g. her correspondence with Claude Lanzmann, but also by showing how media, in extremely anti-feminist and patriarchal senses, tried to display de Beauvoir as a kind of sidekick plaything for Jean-Paul Sartre.returnreturnThe woman Beauvoir became was partly the result of her own choices. However, Beauvoir was acutely aware of the tension between being a cause of herself and a product of othersâ making, of the conflict between her own desires and othersâ expectations. For centuries French philosophers had debated the question of whether it is better to live life seen or unseen by others. Descartes claimed (borrowing Ovidâs words) that âto live well you must live unseenâ.returnreturnSartre would write reams about the objectifying âgazeâ of other people â which he thought imprisoned us in relations of subordination. Beauvoir disagreed: to live well human beings must be seen by others â but they must be seen in the right way.returnreturnThis book weaves together what de Beauvoir stood for, believed in, constructed, changed, and championed, throughout her life. Itâs a chronological book where Kirkpatrick has gone to lengths to excise de Beauvoir from the myths that have sadly followed her legacy around. Kirkpatrick shows, with clarity, how both magazines and translators have misconstrued and obscured what de Beauvoir created. Here is one example:returnreturnIn spring 1953 the first English translation of The Second Sex was published. Blanche Knopf, the wife of the publisher Alfred Knopf, had heard people talking about it when she was in Paris. Her French wasnât good enough to assess the work herself; she thought it was some kind of intellectual sex manual so she asked a professor of zoology to write a readerâs report. H. M. Parshley wrote back praising it as âintelligent, learned, and wellbalancedâ; it was ânot feminist in any doctrinaire senseâ. The Knopfs wrote back: would he like to translate it? And please could he cut it down a bit? (Its author, Knopf said, suffered from âverbal diarrheaâ.) In French, The Second Sex was 972 pages long. In correspondence with Knopf, Parshley said he was cutting or condensing 145 of them â deleting nearly 15 per cent of what Beauvoir said.returnreturnParshley had no background in philosophy or French literature, and he missed many of the rich philosophical connotations and literary allusions of Beauvoirâs original French, making her look much less rigorously philosophical than she was. He also cut sections and translated material in less- than-innocent ways. The hardest hit section was the one on womenâs history, where he deleted seventy- eight womenâs names and almost every reference to socialist forms of feminism. He cut references to womenâs anger and oppression but kept references to menâs feelings. He cut Beauvoirâs analysis of housework.returnreturnWhen she saw what Parshley had cut, Beauvoir wrote back that âso much of what seems important to me will have been omittedâ. He wrote back saying that the book would be âtoo longâ if he didnât cut it, so Beauvoir asked him to state outright in the preface that he had made omissions and condensed her work. But he was not as forthright as she hoped.returnreturnIn America the book was not billed as an âexistentialistâ work because Blanche Knopf thought existentialism was a âdead duckâ; she had, in fact, asked Parshley to play it down in his preface. When Parshleyâs preface appeared he said that since âMlle de Beauvoirâs book is, after all on woman,not on philosophyâ he had âdone some cutting and condensation here and there with a view to brevityâ.â Practically all such modifications,â he writes, âhave been made with the authorâs express permission.âreturnreturnIn a 1985 interview Beauvoir said that she begrudged Parshley âa great dealâ. (A new English translation, with the missing pieces restored, would not be published until 2009 in Britain, 2010 in America.)returnreturnI recently reviewed Deirdre Bairâs Parisian Lives: Samuel Beckett, Simone de Beauvoir, and Me: A Memoir, that only to a limited extent works as commentary on Bairâs biography of de Beauvoir. Bair makes it clear that de Beauvoir wanted to present anything but a one-dimensional picture of herself; Kirkpatrick comments on the memoir by including correspondence and diary entries to flesh everything out, to paint a final picture.returnreturnI do not think Kirkpatrick claims to have painted a final version of de Beauvoir as she clearly recognises her subject to have been a multi-faceted being, as with most humans. This is how Kirkpatrick paints her: an extraordinary human who downplayed her own role in different areas of life, while constantly changing herself, á la Epicurus.returnreturnreturnJean-Paul Sartre, Maurice Merleau-Ponty, unknown, Simone de BeauvoirreturnKirkpatrick does not shy from displaying de Beauvoirâs mental riches, achievements, and critique.returnreturnWhen discussing that Sartre incorporated de Beauvoirâs ideas in his Being and Nothingness and criticising him for parts of his book and philosophical theory:returnreturn⦠claiming that Sartre âstoleâ Beauvoirâs ideas is problematic, both historically and philosophically. Historically, it is problematic because their relationship was one of âconstant conversationâ and mutual (if not exactly reciprocal) intellectual encouragement. And philosophically, it is problematic because both Beauvoir and Sartre were steeped in French philosophical sources that neither of them bothered to cite in their works, let alone claimed to own.returnreturnAn additional difficulty arises because initially Beauvoir was the kind of philosopher who thought that what mattered about a philosophy was not who had the idea; what mattered was whether it was true or not. In the 1940s, she would be very critical of the concept of âpossessionâ. But she was also very critical of Sartre. Later in life she would realize that the idea of possession plays an important role in the perpetuation of power, and who is remembered by posterity. Being and Nothingness contained a concept that Beauvoir and Sartre had discussed together throughout the 1930s. It was present in When Things of the Spirit Come First and went on to inform Beauvoirâs later work in powerful ways. But it was Sartre who would become famous for it: bad faith.returnreturnIn her memoirs Beauvoir said that âweâ discussed bad faith when describing the emergence of this concept in their thinking in the 1930s. As Sartre described it in Being and Nothingness, bad faith was a way of fleeing from freedom, which consists in over- identifying with either âfacticityâ or âtranscendenceâ.returnreturnFacticity stands for all of the contingent and unchosen things about you such as the time or place in which you were born, the colour of your skin, your sex, your family, your education, your body. And âtranscendenceâ refers to the freedom to go beyond these features to values: this concerns what you choose to make of the facts, how you shape yourself through your actions. For Sartre, bad faith arises when facticity and transcendence are out of joint in a way that makes an individual think they are determined to be a certain way. He gave the famous example of a waiter: he is in bad faith if he thinks his facticity â i.e., the fact that he is a waiter â determines who he is. The waiter is always free to choose another path in life; to deny this is to deny his transcendence. On the other hand, if the waiter thinks it doesnât matter that he is a waiter when he applies to be a CEO, then he is in bad faith for the opposite reason: he has failed to recognize the limits of his facticity.returnreturnThis might sound trivial â but what if you replace the word âwaiterâ with the word âJewâ or âwomanâ or âblackâ? Human history is full of examples of people reducing other people to a single dimension of their facticity and, in doing so, failing to recognize their full humanity. In 1943, it was crystal clear that that habit did not only belong to humanityâs past. But Sartre didnât make this ethical move in Being and Nothingness. Nor did he give a satisfactory answer to the ethical problem of objectifying others there. Rather, he said that we must not take ourselves to be determined by our facticity â because whatever the conditions of our existence, we are free to make the most of them.returnreturnAlready in the 1930s Beauvoir was convinced that this was wrong. Sartre thought human beings were free because whatever their situation they were free to âtranscendâ facticity by choosing between different ways of responding to it. Her challenge was this: âWhat sort of transcendence could a woman shut up in a harem achieve?â There is a difference between having freedom (in the sense of being theoretically able to make a choice) and having the power to choose in the actual situation where your choice has to be made. She would go on to articulate her philosophical criticisms in two philosophical essays in the 1940s, Pyrrhus and Cinéas and The Ethics of Ambiguity, but in the meantime she had to deal with the fallout from She Came to Stay in her personal life.returnreturnreturnSimone de Beauvoir, photographed by Henri Cartier-Bresson.returnTheir relationship was interwoven, to and fro, throughout their lives:returnreturnIn the memoirs Beauvoir said that the only thing that might have changed her mind about joining this bourgeois institution was children. And while in her teens she expected to be a mother she no longer foresaw this as a possible future: she had come to see childbearing as âa purposeless and unjustifiable increase of the worldâs populationâ.58 Whether for rhetorical or genuine reasons, Beauvoir frames her decision not to have children in terms of her vocation: a Carmelite nun âhaving undertaken to pray for all mankind, also renounces the engendering of individual human beingsâ. She knew she needed time and freedom in order to write. So, as she saw it, âBy remaining childless I was fulfilling my proper functionâ.returnreturnSo, instead of marrying, Beauvoir and Sartre revised the terms of their pact: their relationship had become closer and more demanding than it had been when they first made it. Now they decided that although brief separations were permissible, long solitary sabbaticals were not. Their new promise was not life- long; they decided they would reconsider the question of separation when they entered their thirties. So although Marseille would separate them, Beauvoir left Paris on a firmer footing â with a clearer future â with Sartre.returnreturnSimone de Beauvoir with Claude Lanzmann, left, and Jean-Paul Sartre.returnPhotograph: Bettmann/Bettmann ArchivereturnSimone de Beauvoir with Claude Lanzmann, left, and Jean-Paul Sartre.returnPhotograph: Bettmann/Bettmann ArchivereturnThis book contains many elements of de Beuvoirâs life: love, academia, writing novels, critique, her extreme ups and downs with people, for example Nelson Ahlgrenâ¦returnreturnThis book is very well constructed: its elements are in place and paint a full picture. de Beauvoir stands as a full human being in this book, which is both sobering and cleansing; this book is not a hagiography, thank Bog.returnreturnI recommend to read this book and also Sarah Bakewellâs brilliant At the Existentialist Café: Freedom, Being, and Apricot Cocktails.